All living systems show two opposing tendencies: the tendency to creative discovery, and the tendency to conservative rigidity. Every living system exhibits both tendencies but in widely differing proportions. Moreover, the relation between the two tendencies is not symmetrical: it's fair to say that while creativity requires a modicum of conservatism, too much of the latter can and often does stifle the former completely.
There is, clearly, a difference between making a living and having a life.
Human life is, indeed all sentient life is, to a very great extent about making a living. But if that's all it is about, then such a life is seriously impoverished, however successful the living. Making a living implies, as it does in the natural world, specialisation. For better or for worse, one becomes to a great extent what one does. We become some identifiable type of human function in the course of making our living. We are urged, as children to be something. We do this with greater or lesser degrees of coherence. We become doctors, lawyers, factory-workers, toilet-cleaners, musicians, artists, astronauts, beggars, tycoons, thieves and so on. Each of these functions implies a degree of specialisation and normally, the more complete the specialisation, the more successfully the function is performed. But if this success is the reward of specialisation, the price paid is very often the loss of plasticity, the loss of adaptability, the loss of creative formlessness, creative infinity. We all know of people who are so completely formed (or deformed) by their professional activity that they cannot stop performing that particular function. The lawyer adopts litigious attitudes in his relations with his family and friends. The teacher remains a pedagogue, even between the sheets. The doctor cannot stop diagnosing illness and so on. To a greater or lesser extent, we all become a function of our role in life. To a greater or lesser extent, our minds are structured by our function. Our function turns into a mental carapace.
We think of knowledge as liberating, but it can turn into quite the reverse. While learning expands the mind, knowledge can frequently limit it. To a greater or lesser extent, we become a function of our knowledge and see the world through the spectacles that our knowledge imposes upon our minds. This sort of functionalisation happens not only with respect to specialised, professional knowledge, it also happens with respect to beliefs of all kinds as well. The mind operates according to the categories set by the beliefs and functions and may be unable to stand outside of them. Often such functionalisation of the mind – though necessary to making a living – results in rigidity of attitude, all kinds of orthodoxy, dogmatism and occasionally, bigotry. The efficient and successful performance of a function often correlates with the degree to which the mind in question is ‘orthodox’, ‘dogmatic’ or ‘bigoted’. Less than whole-minded commitment diminishes efficiency. The result of all of these limitations on the human mind is a diminution of both the world inhabited and of the self that inhabits such a world. When it goes too far, functionalisation is a matter of living as a part self in a part world, living as a fragment in a collection of fragments. Such functionalisation, when yoked to the paranoid emotions of the ego can become a negative, damaging state in which each specialised individual pursues individual goals to the detriment of others. When belief in the thing-ideology and the fragmentation it engenders intervene to reinforce this negative development, the individual becomes the famous cog in the machine and the result is quite simply catastrophic. Dehumanised units interact mechanically with each other according to the forces generated by the immediate tensions to which they are subject and humanity disappears.
Human life is, indeed all sentient life is, to a very great extent about making a living. But if that's all it is about, then such a life is seriously impoverished, however successful the living. Making a living implies, as it does in the natural world, specialisation. For better or for worse, one becomes to a great extent what one does. We become some identifiable type of human function in the course of making our living. We are urged, as children to be something. We do this with greater or lesser degrees of coherence. We become doctors, lawyers, factory-workers, toilet-cleaners, musicians, artists, astronauts, beggars, tycoons, thieves and so on. Each of these functions implies a degree of specialisation and normally, the more complete the specialisation, the more successfully the function is performed. But if this success is the reward of specialisation, the price paid is very often the loss of plasticity, the loss of adaptability, the loss of creative formlessness, creative infinity. We all know of people who are so completely formed (or deformed) by their professional activity that they cannot stop performing that particular function. The lawyer adopts litigious attitudes in his relations with his family and friends. The teacher remains a pedagogue, even between the sheets. The doctor cannot stop diagnosing illness and so on. To a greater or lesser extent, we all become a function of our role in life. To a greater or lesser extent, our minds are structured by our function. Our function turns into a mental carapace.
We think of knowledge as liberating, but it can turn into quite the reverse. While learning expands the mind, knowledge can frequently limit it. To a greater or lesser extent, we become a function of our knowledge and see the world through the spectacles that our knowledge imposes upon our minds. This sort of functionalisation happens not only with respect to specialised, professional knowledge, it also happens with respect to beliefs of all kinds as well. The mind operates according to the categories set by the beliefs and functions and may be unable to stand outside of them. Often such functionalisation of the mind – though necessary to making a living – results in rigidity of attitude, all kinds of orthodoxy, dogmatism and occasionally, bigotry. The efficient and successful performance of a function often correlates with the degree to which the mind in question is ‘orthodox’, ‘dogmatic’ or ‘bigoted’. Less than whole-minded commitment diminishes efficiency. The result of all of these limitations on the human mind is a diminution of both the world inhabited and of the self that inhabits such a world. When it goes too far, functionalisation is a matter of living as a part self in a part world, living as a fragment in a collection of fragments. Such functionalisation, when yoked to the paranoid emotions of the ego can become a negative, damaging state in which each specialised individual pursues individual goals to the detriment of others. When belief in the thing-ideology and the fragmentation it engenders intervene to reinforce this negative development, the individual becomes the famous cog in the machine and the result is quite simply catastrophic. Dehumanised units interact mechanically with each other according to the forces generated by the immediate tensions to which they are subject and humanity disappears.
The mind is always in danger of becoming no more than a
function of its beliefs and when the ego is in control of those beliefs, its
craving for power is such that, to talk mythically for a moment, it ousts God
by assuming his role. There are only these two possibilities, given the
propensity of the mind to become functionalised by its beliefs: either the ego
fuses with the self and the self recognises its dependence upon an overarching
meaning to which it is subservient, or the ego sees itself as sole authority,
the sole origin of meaning in the universe and abolishes God in order to take
his place. By ‘God’ here is meant no more than a meaning to the universe that
is not simply that of the ego. God’s place is taken by the ego’s claim to
godlike knowledge and what goes with it, god-like control. The scientific ego
is the last refuge of anthropomorphic religion; here the ego has fused with the
anthropomorphic god. The ego as quasi-divine lawgiver arrogates to itself the
omniscience and the omnipotence of the monotheistic deity. Its mechanistic
universe is ruled by laws that it has itself created. These laws are forced
upon the rest of mankind by so-called ‘proof’, a form of violence that is
generated by nothing more authoritative that what appears self-evident to the
ego and that thus frequently means no more than ‘true because I say so’. What
is self-evident to the ego is what it makes itself, namely its machines, either
the literal machines of technology or the intellectual machines of theory. So
the whole business of ego-authority goes around in a circle and the authority
of ego-based intellection is simply the mechanical propensity of the ego. This
is as close as the ego gets to the status of ens causa sui. It is an
indication of the vacuous nature of an attitude that declares that parts are
more important than wholes: the ego as part imagines that it is entitled to
legislate for the whole and for no good reason than that it both desires to do
so and lacks the ability to conceive of any power above itself. Since the ego
can only work with machines and since the machine is necessarily a
demonstration of its own validity, the ego imagines that the mere appeal to
machine models will be exclusively authoritative. The functionalisation of the intellect makes
every thus functionalised ego infallible in its own eyes. The result is both a
cacophony of little tin gods shouting at each other and a leaden knee-jerk consensus that is the essence of orthodoxy. Daily human life is
analysed in terms of a range of mechanical problems. These problems are
provided with mechanical ‘solutions’ by a variety of tin-pot deities. The
result is that daily life becomes, increasingly, a perpetuation of the very
problems that the solutions were intended to solve. The reason for this is that
the root of the problem lies within the ego and its reductive, mechanical
methods: the rationalistic ego is, in the words of Karl Kraus, “the disease of which it thinks
itself the cure.”
Just as the ideology of mechanism imposes a mechanical
conception of the processes of nature and just as the thing-ideology imposes a
fragmentary view of reality, so the functionalisation of the person succeeds in
rendering all human beings mechanical and fragmentary as well. It must be said
that the success of the ideology is as notable here as it is in the scientific
sphere. It must also be said that the catastrophic effects of functionalisation
on the human self are as extensive and profound as the effects of mechanical
modes of understanding on the environment. The two go together and complement
each other perfectly: the practical policies that result from mechanical models
cooked up by a myopic, hidebound science are implemented with robotic
efficiency and soulless disregard for the fine balances of nature by the
truncated ego- and persona-dominated beings to whom they appeal. The greatest
danger in the human realm today is the possibility that this combination of mechanistic
ideology, mechanised society and mechanised personalities will supplant, by
virtue of their very simplistic efficiency, all other ways of viewing our
world. If this happened and if
centralised political power on this planet were of this cast, it would be time
to bid good-bye to all those vague but precious notions, such as ‘environmental
ethics’, ‘human rights’, ‘the freedom of the individual’, ‘the sanctity of
life’, ‘the mind’, ‘the creative imagination’, ‘the human spirit’ and so on,
which make the functionalised ego sneer, but without which we humans would be a
lot nastier and certainly less creative than we are. These concepts already
have a difficult time of it, but they survive because decent, unprejudiced
people know they are valuable, even though there is no room for them in the
officially scientific view of things. The day this language goes on the wane
and begins to disappear from public discourse in favour of the efficient
language of function and technique, that is the day humanity will begin the
first stage of its congealment into a stagnating or self-destructive species.
It may well be that the human species will split into two,
the one continuing to grow and develop, the other, like the coelacanth settling
down to long-term stability. It may be that that process has already begun.
Whatever the case, the functionalisation of the human person strangles
creativity, reduces the range of the personality to that of a routine-ridden
calculator and chokes off that indeterminate, unpredictable, innovatory input
into the world that is the essence of our interaction with our environment. How
then does the wholly functionalised mind operate? It operates, primarily, by
adhering with almost evangelical fervour to the implementation of a certain procedure,
a certain method, a certain algorithm: it computes. The specific nature of the
functionalisation is given by the role, the persona. The energy for the
sometimes almost fanatical zeal for method is provided by that would-be
divinity, the ego. The combination of functional efficiency and ego-ambition is
one of the most potent in the human world today; and it is this combination
that could result in the imposition of the universal totalitarian machine
portrayed in literature and film from Plato’s Republic to Skinner’s Walden2,
from Fritz Lang’s Metropolis to the ghastly visions of the Matrix
films and of all those other popular stories of ultimate societal mechanisation.
The extent to which such scenarios are viewed positively or negatively depends
upon the degree of mechanisation of the personality doing the viewing. The
point of view adopted here is the following: far from representing a positive
view of the future, such nightmares are wholly negative since they represent
attempts to achieve, for whatever agency or ideology it may be, a control over
humanity that will lift it out of the creative mainstream of evolution and
consign it to the class of no-longer-developing creatures. And that – at least
for humanity as we know it – would be a very bad thing indeed.
So how does functionalisation of the person work? It works
by developing, to the detriment of the self as a whole, the rational,
methodical aspects of the intellect – the left-brain aspects, in the language of brain-mythology – and
by linking these so firmly with a certain role within a certain organisation or
a certain type of organisation, that the person concerned is entrapped and enslaved - bought, body and soul. It becomes incapable of thinking outside of a certain
box or outside of certain boxes. This role is defined as a series of procedures
for which the person has responsibility. This sense of responsibility is
cemented by many types of reward, financial gain, status, power, influence and
the like, that are craved by the self-worshipping ego. The old animal passions
that stoke the ego – territoriality,
aggressivity towards any competition, self-importance, self-regard,
vengefulness, greed, and the like, on the one hand – and the distortions that
result from the truncation of the self from its own depths – paranoia and
schizoid dissociation of intellect from emotions, on the other – create an
extremely efficient, intense but dangerously unstable state of mind that is a
diminution of the human. It is a diminution of the human because it constitutes
a loss of that distance and ‘beyondness’, a loss of the finite-infinite
tension, that always characterises the relation of the self to its own
products: the infinite self externalising itself in finite productions. The functionalised personality is pure persona, pure ego and the
robotic attitudes that go along with this are deeply pathological, however
‘normal’ they may be considered in our western industrialised societies. The
instability of a functionalised personality depends upon the strength of those
creative forces of renewal that are part of the birth-right of the self, and on
the degree to which the function has conquered or subjugated them or otherwise
keeps them in check. In certain functionalised personalities, the function
cannot keep the transformatory forces in a state of repression and they break
out (often in a ‘mid-life crisis’) either in positive or in negative form,
either as creative innovation and departure, or as destructive illness. Both of
these latter types of dissolution of the function are relatively rare. The
functionalised person usually has too much to lose by allowing cracks in the
persona to appear. Those who do allow such slippage either achieve something
radically different from their functional prowess or else they suffer some kind
of breakdown and consequent demotion or disgrace.
The functionalised person in short is a mechanised mind.
Small wonder, then that it tends to develop conceptions of the mind that are
mechanical. Its first level of programming is that of the theory of
three-dimensional space, one-dimensional time, and reality as a collection of
three-dimensional solid, persisting objects. This basic operating system of the
mechanised intellect, laid down in early childhood, is then reinforced by the
acquisition of language and becomes the basic set of assumptions used to
approach the world of experience. The next level of programming comes from
education and depends upon the degree to which the personality concerned adopts
mechanised attitudes and mechanised thought-patterns from the milieu in which
it grows to maturity. Those persons possessing a facility for procedural
matters, algorithmic thought-patterns, convergent, rule-governed thinking of
all types will tend to flourish in an educational milieu where such things are
valued and where proficiency in them is rewarded. Educational success,
throughout, will have been measured in terms of the efficiency with which the
person convinces the educational authorities of its ability to conform to
received standards of excellence. The ‘passing’ of examinations, generally no
more than the reproduction of rote-learned factual information or the
manipulation of procedural technique, will further reinforce the sense of
achievement of the already deeply functionalised intellect. The next layer of
programming, however, is probably the most vital, and it is this level that
completes the process of functionalisation: it is the level that is laid upon
the person by professional activity. The need to achieve economic independence
and the ego’s desire for status, drive the already functionalised personality
towards social roles that it can fill with the aid of the mental procedures and
ideological assumptions thus far internalised. The personality is drawn into a
net of forces that provide all manner of feedback loops, which further
functionalise the mind: daily routine, reward, fear of demotion, economic
necessity, social pressure, reputation, authority, deadlines, competition and
so on. The person becomes entirely bound up in the routine of such an
existence, entirely dominated mentally by it and entirely devoted to its partial
values. The result is often either a hard-nosed and ruthless personality who
sees only the achievement of those immediate goals that are imposed by the role
played, or else a stressed and harried personality whose perpetually stimulated
fight or flight mechanisms operate internally and inappropriately to burn up
the body itself.
The thing-ideology and the philosophy of mechanism drive
the procedures and values of the major educational institutions. These, in
turn, foster the functionalised personality. These personalities achieve
eminence both in the educational institutions and in the other organisations to
which they apply their abilities. The mechanised, functionalised values and the
ambitious, energetic ego are highly prized in industry and commerce because
they maximise growth and profit. Governments perceive this maximisation of profit as the
highest good of a country and therefore foster all the values, procedures and
abilities that conduce to its further maximisation. Educational policy,
economic policy and all other sorts of planning then become dominated by the
mechanical outlook and the immediate goals of the functionalised ego. The
result is a drive towards the mechanisation of society from its roots to its
most authoritative institutions, from parenting to governing, from
manufacturing to entertaining, every activity is governed by procedure, by
method, by algorithm; and the intrinsic, indeterminate creativity of the human
mind that is responsible for every positive cultural acquisition is lost.
This tendency of western societies to foster the training
of more and more functionalised persons generates a conception of human
identity that equates it entirely with the persona, with the social role. The
successful person is ‘something’ in society, i.e. a recognisable definable
thing. Personalities are regarded as achieving a state in which they are
‘finished’, ‘formed’, ‘rounded off’. The implication seems to be that once a recognisable
social role has been achieved and filled efficiently, then the person has, as
it were, peaked and can go nowhere else. The person thus functionalised is
entirely identified with the brain with which it is associated and this brain
is considered as a sort of computing device that has been programmed to operate
in a certain way. The functionalised person and the mechanised mind see only mechanism and function; they are self-confirming theories. Inevitably, when the efficiency of this computing device
begins to wane, the person is regarded as waning along with it and hence judged
to be of little use, little worth and, like a clapped-out machine, suitable for the
scrap-heap. The person is regarded as diminishing along with its diminishing
efficiency. The value of such a functionalised person is precisely the extent
to which it can fulfil its function efficiently. Once this goes, the person has
no further value. Thus the old, the sick, the handicapped, the diminished have
no value in terms of functionalised personalities. How long such diminished
persons will continue to be tolerated in a given society depends upon the
extent to which non-functionalised persons and non-functional conceptions of
personal value are maintained. It requires very little for a society to be so
devoted to mechanical values that it begins a process of reification,
objectification or depersonalisation of the persons it regards as somehow
inappropriate to its aims. Thus totalitarianisms of all kinds have
systematically persecuted those they considered inappropriate in this sense,
i.e. not susceptible to being functionalised in the approved manner. Behind all
of these totalitarianisms has always stood some rigid, orthodoxy, mechanically
applied, some mechanistic, algorithmic conception of human life and of the most
efficient manner in which to live it. The
mechanistic-deterministic-materialistic ideology that still governs the west
and the thing-ideology that now constitutes its only authoritative view of the
world, are steadily creating a functionalised population that not only cares
nothing for the indeterminate core of the human self, but also fails to
understand that it is the origin of all that is positive in human culture:
purpose, value, creativity, meaning, and all those forces that foster the
constant achievement of complexity in diversity that has characterised the
history of human culture. The victory of the functionalised personality would
perhaps spell the end of that history; it might spell the ‘end of history’
altogether, in Francis Fukuyama’s phrase.
The antidote to functionalisation is not to be found in
its demonisation or in any set of measures designed to achieve its abolition.
Functionalisation produces many benefits. It focuses the intellect with the
intensity of a laser-beam and this intensity of vision permits an attention to
detail and an unsurpassed analytical ability that are both of great value in
the solving of all manner of ancient human problems – disease, hunger, ignorance,
privation, and suchlike. On the other hand, it is clear that unchecked
functionalisation produces its own set of problems – intolerance,
insensitivity, short-termism, myopia of all kinds, diminution of the person and
so on. The solution therefore would seem to be some means of maintaining the
benefits of functionalisation while reducing its deleterious effects. This can
only be done, it seems, by fostering two mutually opposing manners of thought.
The self has to be seen as potentially governed by contradictory sets of
principles. Once again, the solution to a fundamental conflict in human life is
not the stressing of one side to the exclusion of the other, but rather the
balanced maintenance of both elements of the tension. The procedure-obsessed, methodical,
algorithmic aspects of the personality have to be counterbalanced by its
informal, indeterminate, unpredictable aspects and the two have to be seen as
one.
In circumstances where functionalised thought-patterns
rule the roost – as in contemporary western civilisation – individuals will
tend to see method as the essence of thought. When you have no creative ideas,
you fall back on a method. The logical procedure, the mathematical procedure,
the organisational principle, the managerial method, the recipe, the formula,
the formalism, the routine – all of these will be seen as ends in themselves
and not as provisional thought-patterns, essentially subject to review and
modification. In addition formal patterns of thought will be regarded as
somehow complete and in themselves completely authoritative. Formal thought
will be considered to generate its own internal principles from its own formal
structure. The form will be accorded absolute status. No attention will be paid
to the status of the self as always above and beyond its own formal thought, as
the indeterminate and indefinable origin and creator of all formality and as
the authoritative user and manipulator of such formalism rather than merely its
slavish operator. It is therefore only in the affirmation of the self’s
intrinsic indefinability that such a viewpoint can be achieved. The finite,
limited aspects of the mind have to be seen as dependent upon an infinite and
unlimited background. The essentially extra-systemic nature of the self has to
be affirmed. Once the self is seen as dominated by particular procedures,
particular formalisms rather than as being essentially above them, the self is
on the road to mechanisation and functionalisation. Where thought is largely
driven by repeatable formulae, intelligence has to be seen as the intrinsically
indefinable essence of the self and the indeterminate source of the determined
structures it creates. Intelligence has to be regarded as the unformalisable
origin of all formality. Intelligence is only formalised when it manipulates a
formalism. As the origin of all formalisms, it is intrinsically superior to
them. This is not mystification, it is simply good mental hygiene. Though they
are among our most intimate experiences, we have no clear idea how the innovations
of the human intellect take place. We have no formal procedure for the
achievement of creative advance. We have no way of formalising the production
of new structure by the human mind. Thus we have to accept the gifts of our own
creativity on trust. It is in that sense that the essential nature of the self
has to be considered to be indefinable and indeterminate. Thus any fostering of
the functionalisation of the intellect – and such is vital if the intellect is
to achieve and to master any field – has to be offset by an inculcation of the
essential inviolability of the self, the essential ‘beyondness’ or infinity of
the self, the essential, indefinable value of the self. It is perhaps in the
use of the traditional language of ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’ that such a view had been
and is currently maintained in our society. But such language is on the wane
and its vocabulary lacks resonance. We have to find an equally powerful
language that renders the same service as the traditional but now discredited
concepts. The language of physics is perhaps now in a position to do this for
us, particularly where it points up the spurious nature of the distinction
between parts and wholes. If there is
no ultimate separation between the sub-atomic particle as a local manifestation of energy and the entire
energy-field of the entire universe, then a similar lack of separation can be
assumed to obtain in respect to the human being. If the universal energy-field
is imbued with its own universal meaning and ultimately governed by an
indeterminate source of all creativity, then our connectedness to this source
must surely be the antidote to the deleterious effects of our own tendency to
functionalisation. But we have to choose this connectedness.
The functionalised human being is the fragmented human being, the part human being, the human being who is, by virtue of the loss of wholeness, cut off from the world as a whole, from the self as a whole and from humanity as a whole. Such a fragmented human being is responsible for all the ills of the human world today. Such human beings are doubly dangerous in that not only are they alienated and intrinsically distorted, they are also in ignorance or even in denial of the fact. This combination of mental distortion and refusal to understand the distortion is at the root of the cultural malaise of the west and at the origin of its disastrous collective behaviour.
No comments:
Post a Comment